Showing posts with label Black Swans. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Black Swans. Show all posts

Thursday, August 25, 2016

Wherein I Take the @nntaleb IYI Test & Fail

Your image of this writer
Herr Doktor Professor: stern master
I’m going to take the Nassim Nicholas Taleb (NNT) test to determine if I am an IYI (“intellectual yet idiot”). Of course, right off the bat you can see I’m trying to play chess with Washington Square hustlers or a pick-up game with NBA studs—I’m out of my league here. I’m not an intellectual, I’m not an academic, and I don’t write for a living outside of legal briefs and memos. I’m just a practicing lawyer. But I do have an abiding interest in ideas. I’ve always been fascinated by how the world works, how it came to this point, and how we might tinker with it. I've enjoyed and believe that I've benefited from reading NNT's books (Bed of Procrustes excepted). But I must emphasize, unlike NNT, I’m an amateur, not a flâneur.

So with my disqualifications in place, let me go through the NNT test, line-by-line, to obtain my ranking. Taleb’s criteria are in plain type followed by my responses in italics.

What's IYI?

 Intellectual Yet Idiot:  [I just said, I’m not an intellectual. Whether I’m an idiot or not is open to further discussion. I imagine—nay, know—there are compelling arguments in the affirmative for this conclusion]

semi-erudite bureaucrat [I am not now nor have I ever been a member of the bureaucratic party. I’ve been either in a partnership or self-employed for about 30 years]

who thinks he is an erudite [I aspire to erudition, I do not claim it];

pathologizes others for doing things he doesn't understand not realizing it is his understanding that may be limited [Maybe, sometimes. Who hasn’t made this error?];

imparts normative ideas to others [Like NNT?]:

thinks people should act according to their best interests [A question of definition here: narrowly or broadly defined? And note “should”, not “do”]

*and* he knows their interests, particularly if they are uneducated "red necks" or English non-crisp-vowel class. [Well, to some extent, yes. I’ve had people pay me for my advice & opinions for over 30 years. On the other hand, I hope I have some sense of humility. Do you know this word, “humility”?]

More socially
subscribes to the New Yorker [Yes, I do. Are you suggesting Paris Match instead? In the New Yorker I skip the ads and focus more than I should on the cartoons; indeed, we have a whole book of New Yorker cartoons—quite fun. Is there a penalty for having a New Yorker book--or two?];

never curses on twitter [Although known on occasion to use profane, scatological, or crude language in person, I abjure it in public discourse. There’s already enough vulgarity out there—plus someone would always out do me.  I do, however, admit to excessive snark on Twitter. Perhaps there’s a New Year’s resolution in there]; 

speaks of "equality of races" and "economic equality" but never went out drinking with a minority cab driver [We’ll I’ve lived and hung with people of different races, and I’m in favor of a greater degree of economic equality than what we currently experience. I grew up middle-class in a small Iowa town where rich kids (by local standards) pretty much had to mingle in school with poorer ones because there was only one school and too few of us to avoid some mingling. As to drinking with a cab driver, no; but with my fellow road construction workers? Oh, yeah. It was, you may say, satisfactory]; 

has considered voting for Tony Blair [N/A. I’m not a Brit! But I did vote for Bill Clinton 2x & will for HRC (see below)];

has attended more than 1 TEDx talks and watched more than 2 TED talks [Never been to a TED Talk, but I’ve watched more than two. I rather like them on the whole. I’ve also watched NNT on YouTube at festivals (presumably not literary and not in the UK). How does that score? BTW, some of my favorite peeps have given a TED Talk]; 

will vote for Hillary Monsanto-Malmaison because she seems electable [Deferred to the finale];

has The Black Swan on his shelves [I have two copies: one hardcover in storage & one on my Kindle. Do I get extra credit?]

but mistakes absence of evidence for evidence of absence [It’s a catchy slogan but I have to bone up to determine if the converse is also true: absence of evidence may be evidence of absence. In which case, how do we distinguish the two instances? I will say this from my humble perch as a practicing attorney: try convincing a judge or a jury that X exists when you have no evidence (an absence of evidence) that X exists—a case not to take on a contingent fee. If I find no evidence of tigers in my yard (sightings, paw prints, scats, animal carcasses, etc.), then it's highly likely—although not certain—that there are no tigers in my yard. Despite appropriate and convincing examples in The Black Swan, NNT tries to skate too far with this slogan];

is member of a club to get traveling privileges [no, just credit card miles; no clubs. I wouldn’t want to belong to any club that would have me as a member!];

if social scientist uses statistics without knowing how they are derived [Not a social scientist. I’m respectful but wary of statistics, suspicious that they may conceal lies and damned lies];

when in the UK goes to literary festivals [I’ve never been to a literary festival in the UK, but when in India I go to the Jaipur Literature Festival. How did you like your sojourn there, NNT?];

drinks red wine with steak (never white) [Usually red, but then I’m from the Midwest and care more about the steak anyway];

used to believe that fat was harmful and has now completely reversed [True--after learning about Art DeVany in NNT’s Fooled By Randomness (read in 2007), and then on to Gary Taubes, Mark Sisson and other others of their ilk];

takes statins because his doctor told him so [No, not necessary. Good cholesterol profile because of good fats; see the previous answer];

fails to understand ergodicity and when explained forgets about it soon later [Got me! I’ll check it on Wikipedia later. Allowed?];

doesn't use Yiddish words [Only a schmuck wouldn’t!];

studies grammar before speaking a language [no, my wife—an ESL teacher—wouldn’t let me be so foolish. Besides I need to eat and use the restroom];

has a cousin who worked with someone who knows the Queen [Really? Come on, are all your readers from the UK? I don’t have a Queen];

has never read Frederic Dard [Who? Okay, you got me. But have you read Hammett, Chandler, McDonald, Elmore, Greenleaf—you know, authors that others read? Okay, the last name was a plug for my cousin],

Michael Oakeshott [no, on my list to read, but you’ve read Collingwood & rate him ahead of Oakeshott, correct?],

 John Gray [short pieces only],

or Joseph De Maistre [read about him in the autumn of 1975 in Shklar’s After Utopia & he didn’t seem worth my time; on review, he still doesn’t. Time better spent on Burke. Yes, I know, but Burke is Anglo-Irish and writes in English]; 

has never gotten drunk with Russians and went breaking glasses [Guilty, but I don’t feel guilty];

doesn't know the difference between Hecate and Hecuba [Not off the top of my head, no]; 

doesn't know that there is no difference between "pseudointellectual" and "intellectual" [I’m not sure, but you’ll tell me]; 

has mentioned quantum mechanics at least twice in the past 5 years [No, I don’t understand it, although from what I know, it is intriguing];

knows at any point in time what his words or actions are doing to his reputation [I follow GW (for non-Americans, George Washington) do attempt to maintain a good reputation. I don’t buy the Trumpian notion that any publicity is good publicity.]

But a much easier marker: doesn't deadlift. [I do, but not as often as I should. Do you get credit for kettlebell swings and standing presses? Pavel would give me credit]

The IYI, Taleb adds, look down at the great unwashed Plebes who haven't read Foucault in college [Mme neither, I’m too old, he wasn’t a big deal then]

and treat them like crap - as if they were inferior forms of life incapable of directing their own affairs. [Nope, I don’t truck with that attitude].

But when you make them feel uncultured, lacking in intellect, and unlearned, like all bureaucrao-journalists, being all tawk, they get very queasy: hit them where it hurts.

They are arrogant down, they will be arrogantified from up.

Speaking of arrogance, back to my deferred answer about “will vote for Hillary Monsanto-Malmaison because she seems electable.” A few words:

NNT is using—what is to his mind—guilt by association. Perhaps it’s my attorney-mind or perhaps my wishful thinking that reason can ultimately trump [irony] innuendo, but I have to call “baloney!” on this. (I concede demerits here for not swearing.) Maybe NNT has a good argument about Monsanto and GMOs. As a matter of personality and pragmatics, I give a lot of credence to the precautionary principle. But a lot of those who’ve given these issues serious thought disagree with NNT about the safety of GMOs. I don’t claim to have a definitive answer. Nor does Hillary Clinton, I suspect. (Neither on her campaign website nor in an issues Wikipedia entry could I find anything about GMOs.)  The meme NNT wants to draw upon is that HRC is an insider and therefore in cahoots with multi-national corporations who want to mess with our food while lining their pockets. (Can I get credit for “cahoots” as exotic, albeit not Yiddish?)  Well, okay, the part about the corporations is probably true, but it assumes a naïve understanding of what a person—even a president—knows or can do about any particular issue, especially one not likely to affect the outcome of an election.

The other point is that I support Hillary Clinton for president. I don’t do so because she’s “electable”, I do so because she is the best choice for my vote, and has been since the beginning of the primary season. An unusually large number of people want to kvetch (award Yiddish use points please) about the candidates this year, and if it makes them feel better, go ahead. As Clay Shirky has so persuasively explained, in the end, one of two persons will be elected the next president. One is an experienced prototypical politician with insider experience and credentials—thank goodness! (Non-swearing demerit acknowledged.)  The other is a demagogue. Each election tests a voter’s political intelligence and savvy in deciding whom to vote for or (if politically active), whom to support. But this year it isn’t just a test of political judgment, it’s a test of character and of fundamental issues of political morality. To suggest otherwise is reprehensible.


And if supporting Hillary Clinton means I fail the test, then screw the test! (Can I get half-credit for this last phrase, Herr Doktor Professor?)

Wednesday, April 17, 2013

Thinking Like a Lawyer & Antifragility

Thinking like a lawyer is what law school is supposed to be all about, and to some extent, it is. Now many people, like Daniel Pink or Gerry Spence, agree that is true--and woe to us all. And to some extent, that also is true. Word nitpicking, “word gravel” (Spence), and endlessly argumentative perspectives (for the purpose of delay or battle by attrition) are all too common in the legal profession. But I want to emphasize a more positive way of thinking about this topic. In fact, I want to consider legal thinking in the context of how lawyers tell laypeople to think about the legal issues put to them, because in this case—especially with juries—we have to put our perspectives in terms that everyone should be able to grasp. 

The Legal System, Torts, and Negligence

I’ve thought about this because I’ve recently finished Nassim N. Taleb’s Antifragile, his intriguing (further) consideration of how risks can affect us. Because I will review the work in a separate post, I won’t go on at length here about the many aspects of the book, but I do want to point to some salient features. One, following a pattern that NNT set forth in his two previous books, Fooled by Randomness and The Black Swan, he favors practitioners over academics. He preaches empirical skepticism from a linage coming starting with Menodotus of Nicomedia through Sextus Empiricus down to the present. He criticizes much of academic medicine because of its rationalist (as opposed to empirical, skeptical) mindset. The mindset that he criticizes says, “If we can do it, we should”, which leads us to think that we can fix a problem by doing this or that without consideration of system effects. He offers a number of examples that make sense. 

However, one thing that he doesn’t address much is lawyers and the common law legal system.* Perhaps it’s because he’s only been exposed to contract-drafters and securities regulators, the sorts of attorneys who attempt to extinguish risk and minimize every manner of Black Swan. Unfortunately, he doesn’t address the common law world of tort laws, for instance. Tort law developed in the U.S. in part as a response to increasing industrialization and commercialization. In short, we had more not governed by contract or status. We had a number of more casual but often consequential interactions that required the law to decide who lost and who gained in such interactions. For instance, who paid what to whom if farmer Brown’s cow was on the railway track and was struck by the train? (Such collisions could damage the train, but the cow usually came up the worst; locomotives have cowcatchers, but cows don't have train catchers.) With the advent of automobiles, all of this became much worse. Now autos could run into trains and to each other. So how did the law respond? 

Following a pattern laid down in the British Isles before the American Revolution, the courts laid down principles on a case-by-case basis, using prior decisions as precedents to establish the norms for later courts and parties to follow. This system dealt with the practicalities of the law at the level of actual litigants and in light of practical necessities. This should make NNT happy: practitioner and practice-based guidelines established according to need. Of course, sometimes the system seemed too overgrown and complex and needed some rational pruning (my Garden metaphor again!), but generally, the rationalization process was a distillation and not a complete overhaul. Some standardization occurred, but not a huge amount. One state could look at what another was doing and could adopt or reject a practice as it saw fit. What works in Iowa might not work in California or New York, but it might prove quite useful (and enlightened) in Nebraska. 

Consider the legal concept of negligence, from the realm of torts described above, which attempts to weigh whether a loss suffered by an injured party (plaintiff) should shift to another party when the plaintiff believes the defendant should have acted differently to avoid the plaintiff’s loss. The plaintiff can shift the loss (obtain a judgment for damages) to the defendant, if the plaintiff can prove by a preponderance of the evidence (more about burdens and evidence later in this essay) that defendant should have acted to prevent the harm from occurring.

We say that defendant had a duty to act to prevent the harm from occurring by acting as a reasonable person would act under like or similar circumstances. The logic of negligence most widely known in legal circles comes from the decision of Judge Learned Hand in U.S. v. Carroll, a case about a barge that broke loose and sank after a tow ship accidentally severed a line anchoring the barge to a pier. The U.S. government, owner of the barge, sued the tow ship (Carroll) for the damages caused, alleging negligence. Justice Hand established a “calculus” of negligence that has remained quite influential throughout the years:
         
[T]he owner's duty, as in other similar situations, to provide against resulting injuries is a function of three variables: (1) The probability that she will break away; (2) the gravity of the resulting injury, if she does; (3) the burden of adequate precautions. Possibly it serves to bring this notion into relief to state it in algebraic terms: if the probability be called P; the injury, L; and the burden, B; liability depends upon whether B is less than L multiplied by P: i.e., whether B < PL.

To expand on this, one can state: If (Burden < Cost of Injury × Probability of occurrence), then the accused will not have met the standard of care required. If (Burden ≥ Cost of injury × Probability of occurrence), then the accused may have met the standard of care.

This classic formula has served at the touchstone of thinking about negligence since it was written in the Carroll decision back in 1947. When you think of the issue in this manner, it makes a lot of sense to formulate things this way. Analytically, it’s very clear and concise. Of course, in practice, it’s much messier. Indeed, as any experienced tort lawyer will tell you (or the Iowa Rules of Appellate Procedure for that matter), questions of negligence are normally decided by applying the principles to the facts of the case, and what does or does not constitute negligence normally lies with the fact-finder, which is usually the jury. Thus, predicting what is or is not negligence becomes difficult because the issue is by definition fact and context-specific; indeed, juries bring in attitudes from their communities that vary over time and place. For instance, what juries accepted as negligence 30 years ago might be rejected today because of changing community attitudes (from business interests campaign against tort claims brought against them) or by distance (how a jury might dispose of a claim can vary from place to place (and even jury to jury). All of this remains decentralized and ad hoc, thus allowing change over time without recourse to the political process (for the most part; much of so-called “tort reform” is an instance to trying to freeze the system to limit damages set by jurors for injury awards). To the extent juries aren’t limited by new reforms, this most democratic (in both its good and bad manifestations) process allows some predictability overall while allowing for change and individual variations over time and place. This, to me, seems a workable system, for all of its faults, which I’ve come to know well in the course of over 30 years of practice. 

Burden of Proof

Another key area where I think that the law has some useful insights to offer all of us concerns the burden of proof. Specifically, who has the burden of proving (or disproving) a proposition (e.g., “Jerry was negligent and this injured me”) and how much proof is necessary for an actor (the court system) to accept that the proposition as proven sufficiently to act upon it (e.g., order Jerry to pay Sandy money for the harm caused by his negligence). 

Generally speaking, a party seeking to establish a proposition has the burden of proving it. In other words, if you want the court to order something, such as payment of money damages or to order a person to refrain from acting via an injunction, you must prove the necessary elements. The standard of proof is the amount of proof necessary to establish a proposition sufficiently for a court to act upon it. In most civil cases in most jurisdictions, this standard is a preponderance of the evidence; in criminal cases, beyond reasonable doubt (and with various other permutations available for less common cases). For instance, for me to obtain a judgment against you for ten million dollars, I need only prove the legally required facts by a preponderance of evidence; however, if the State wants to send me to jail for a day, it must prove all of the legally relevant facts beyond a reasonable doubt. Criminal punishment, including fines, requires a higher standard of proof than a recovery of any sum of money in a civil action.

Think about this in light of the daily decisions that you make. Do you need to know something “beyond reasonable doubt” or by a “preponderance of the evidence”, or perhaps “maybe” works. It depends mostly on the magnitude of the consequences of the decision. Will I like a new ice cream flavor? “Maybe” might provide a sufficient burden of proof for you to try the new flavor. Others may have a higher standard; for instance, another person might believe that she probably will not enjoy the new flavor more than her established favorite (which is chocolate, of course). 

So how skeptically and conservatively (as a matter of judgment, not politics) we may choose to act becomes (to some extent) a function of the magnitude of the risk involved. Let’s take global climate change as an example. On one hand, NNT argues that we are poking Mother Nature with a stick and that we shouldn’t. ("Burden of evidence: The burden of evidence falls on those who disrupt the natural, or those who propose via positiva policies." Antifragile, 429.) The burden, because of the huge consequences if human conduct is upsetting the global climate structure must be upon those who want to maintain the status quo (a via positiva if there ever was one!); i.e., those who don't want to take active steps to counter any human-caused climate change. (Technically, we get into burden-shifting here. In other words, if the plaintiff provides some evidence of proposition A, then the defendant can offer evidence to rebut the proposition, and then the plaintiff must have enough evidence to respond to the defendant’s contrary contention. Plaintiff has the ultimate burden, but it switches back-and-forth during the course of the trial.) 

Blogger, self-experimenter, and UC Berkley-Tsinghua psychology professor Seth Roberts, on the other hand, is a climate change denier. (He will more likely call himself a skeptic and attempt some burden-shifting of his own, but given what I’ve read him to say about this, I think he belongs in the denier camp because of his displays of confirmation bias when considering this the issue.) Like others I’ve read recently, persons I otherwise can find quite persuasive and intelligent, like Roger Scruton and Deirdre McCloskey, suggest that we’re overreacting when we say that we need to change. They argue, I think, that there is no Black Swan (or White Swan, for that matter) of risk, that human-caused global climate change is all a mirage. Roberts and the others argue in effect: 

I know I might be the turkey and they say that there’s this Thanksgiving Day that might terminate my well-being with extreme prejudice, but how do I really know that this will come to pass? I know that I hear the farmer sharpening long, metal blades, talking about this upcoming holiday, and looking longingly at me, but really, this might all be something else. We shouldn’t take any action unless we know for sure that this Thanksgiving thing that you think is coming is proven by  . . . ." 
What, an actual occurrence? This strikes me as a bit late, but that seems to be their preferred position. 

I mention this, because I’ve made lawyerly arguments on Roberts’s blog when this comes up, but my points about burdens and standards of proof don’t elicit a response. I admit that I’m not sure about human-caused global climate change since I don’t have the credentials to independently verify and interpret the data (as I don’t for most of life’s biggest questions). But from what I do know is that if those arguing that we humans are causing global climate change and that there are things that we should be doing to alleviate its impact (it’s beyond stopping now, according to most), then we darned well ought to do all we reasonably can given the magnitude of the risks. (Refer back to the negligence calculus for a refresher on how to think about this.) The climate change deniers don’t seem to want to respond to this. The changes will cause big dislocations (to put it mildly) whether we choose to make changes ourselves or we choose to allow Mother Nature to make them for us. In other words, either our economy changes or Earth's climate changes. 

There are those who might argue that while we’re causing global climate change, we’ll innovate our way out of the pickle. “We’ve done it before and we can do it again and we can do it again.” Maybe. (See Thomas Homer-Dixon’s The Ingenuity Gap about the limits of our ability to innovate our way out of climate change.) However, t this strikes me as a very big gamble, and frankly, one I'd not like to bet upon (I've too much to lose).

All of this may seem quite discursive, but I hope that I’ve made a point that at least in some ways, “thinking like a lawyer” actual can prove useful, albeit demanding. (We don’t like to expend the energy that thinking requires of us, so we dodge it whenever we can). Thinking like a lawyer may not allow us to see Black Swans, but because of the turbulence that lots of everyday decisions in law and business inevitably create, so long as they are disbursed and have some degree of independence should allow a measure of antifragility to arise.
 
* While reviewing Antifragile to make some notes I did find the following, which qualifies the statement made above. I will be looking for any other references to the law as I continue my review: 



The same bottom-up effect applies to law. The Italian political and legal philosopher Bruno Leoni has argued in favor of the robustness of judge-based law (owing to its diversity) as compared to explicit and rigid codifications. True, the choice of a court could be a lottery—but it helps prevent large-scale mistakes. (90)

I argue my effort has been to further elucidate this passing remark.